Einherjar86
Active Member
There's nothing that's universal to all people, but I've yet to hear of a culture where it is uncommon to cry because of death. And even if such a culture does exist, it's the exception to the pattern that characterizes the vast majority of humans on this planet. The patterns that I mentioned are sufficiently common across diverse cultures-many of whom evolved separately- that an explanation is needed. You're zooming in so narrowly into culturally specific ideology that you are dismissing these patterns, which simply leaves your theory lacking in critical respects.
Good point; so, taking that into consideration:
I'm unwilling to say that there is no culture in which it is uncommon to cry because of death. I'm unwilling to say this regarding all cultures that currently exist on this planet; all that ever have, and all that ever will. That point aside, I agree that it is widespread and common to cry over deceased relatives.
But then we should ask why it is common to cry; is this because it is "natural," as you claim, or because our socio-historical conditions have introduced a climate/environment wherein such a relationship is fostered that in turn induces sadness over deceased loved ones? The institution of "love" itself is heavily ideological, not natural in any sense. Mammals certainly take care of their own in many cases; but is this not evolutionary? How do we distinguish between love and evolution? Perhaps it's nothing more than the frustration over an extinguished biological line that led to crying in the first place, which was then sublimated into love after a long period of time.
In this sense, crying over deceased relatives might not be a natural thing at all, but a heavily historically conditioned response.
This is where we disagree. People have certain natural capacities that also condition creation. This is why phenomena like art, music, etc. manifest in cultures that are totally separate from one another. Many of those conditions are inherent to the vast majority of humans (the exceptions being those with certain disabilities or injuries). By ignoring these inherent human (heck, in many cases inherent mammal) qualities you are engaging in a form of reductionism.
Yes, this is an extremely difficult concept to even talk about. I'm going to make a controversial point.
There are processes that pre-date ideology: metabolism, photosynthesis, gene mutation, evolution, erosion, hurricanes, etc. But we cannot claim that the human body, in its most basic non-cultural sense, isn't already ideological; that is, capable of knowing forms (or ideas) of the world. Conceiving of the human in this sense is already to impose ideological parameters upon it; that is, that something called "the human" actually exists. Not the body you inhabit or the bodies around you; but the concept called "the human."
We cannot separate "the human" from the artificial; humanity - indeed, much of life itself - is a technological being. What you want to call natural capacities are, in fact, already institutions that condition an ideological view of the world. Our very senses might be described as ideological; they form the perspective we have on the world. Our entire classification system (i.e. of plants/animals) is based on sight, on that which we can detect by seeing. The process of art - the making of music - reflects and reinforces, by its very creation, the ideological perspective that informs it.
People have certain natural capacities, and art is certainly a trans-cultural phenomenon; but art doesn't reflect pure natural capacity because the very form of art reflects views of the world, and these views are already ideological. You cannot separate the senses themselves from ideology; and these senses then give rise to more complex ideological institutions such as art, music, literature, etc.
In isolation, a body cannot realize the ideological capacity of its apparatus since it cannot realize itself as a thing among other things (other things like it, that is). Once this collective infusion begins - what we might call culture - then we witness the acknowledgement of the senses as instruments in the common effort to know that thing we call "the world." And this common effort produces all kinds various aesthetic and artistic institutions.
I don't think it's reductive to say that all artistic process boils down to ideology. I think it's important to realize that, in a paradoxical sense, ideology already exists prior to artistic creation. Art always presupposes a (purportedly) universal system, just as language cannot function without presupposing a network of words and meanings that precede it.